"More about value judgements in economics"
Wilfred Beckerman’s1
textbook
entitled Economics as Applied Ethics. Value Judgements in Welfare Economics2
has been
published by Palgrave MacMillan. The monograph is intended for students who are
completing their studies of economics and are interested in connections
between economics and ethics. In the Introduction Beckerman states:
“[A]lthough ... the
value judgements inherent in welfare economics are not prominent in economic
research or education, students of the subject, or politicians, ought not to be
left with the impression that economics is a value-free objective science.” (p.
2).
What exactly the author means by
this statement can be fully understood only after reading all 17 chapters of
the book.
In Chapter 1, Fact or value? A
Simple Example: Sustainable Development and the Discount Rate, Beckerman
describes the concept of “sustainable growth” and presents benefits from a
decrease of carbon emissions to the atmosphere. He argues that the “optimal
degree to which we should cut carbon emissions depends on both the ‘facts’
concerning the probability of catastrophic effects on climate, and a number of
ethical considerations.” (p. 14). In particular, these ethical considerations
decide how high we value the welfare of future generations as compared with our
own welfare, or what is the level of the discount rate which is used in an
analysis of costs and benefits of cutting these emissions.
In Chapter 2, Positive
Propositions and Value Judgements, the author reminds the reader of the
distinction between “positive theorems” and “normative theorems”. Positive
theorems inform about what is, and can be true or false. Normative theorems
inform about what should be, and their validity can depend on specific aims
which in turn depend on value judgements (pp. 17–18, also pp. 226–227 in
Chapter 17).
The function of Chapter 3, entitled Fact
and Value in Welfare Economics, is to persuade the reader that postulates
of welfare economics are always based on “positive” economic knowledge and on
value judgements as well. For instance, “positive” economic knowledge tells us
that the stability of prices contributes to economic equality and economic
efficiency. Since economic equality and economic efficiency are generally seen
as desired, or “good”, the conclusion is that we should try to reach the
stability of prices in an economy.
In Chapter 4, From Individuals’
Choices to their “Welfare”, Beckerman analyzes the connection between
market decisions of economic agents, their preferences and their welfare. For
many reasons, e.g. irrational behaviour, asymmetric information, inability to
make use of available information, inability to achieve self-control, and
various forms of altruism, decisions observed on the market cannot accurately
reflect the true preferences and/or the true level of welfare of these
economic agents.
Chapter 5 entitled Pareto
Optimality and the Social Welfare Function analyzes criteria of optimal
allocation of goods in an economy. First, Beckerman describes well-known
limitations of the possibility of practical use of the concept of Pareto
optimum, e.g. the practical impossibility of making compensation payments, a
possible conflict of this concept with society’s value judgements concerning
the distribution of income, and conservation of the status quo. Second,
the Bergson/Samuelson “social welfare function” is analysed, which is based on
an assumption about the possibility of comparing the utility of different
people. At this point, Beckerman reminds the reader of Amartya Sen’s critique
of “welfarism”, or of the assumption about the determination of social welfare
exclusively by the utility of members of society.
In Chapter 6, From Individuals’
Welfare to Social Welfare, the author extends his analysis of obstacles
that make it difficult to transform individuals’ preferences into their economic
decisions and into their welfare, and then into the welfare of society in
general. In the author’s view, the method of linking the measure of the welfare
of the whole society with individuals’ preferences revealed on the market is
unavoidably arbitrary.
In Chapter 7 entitled Utilitarianism
in Welfare Economics, Beckerman analyzes utilitarianism and its link with
the concept of utility maximization as the ethical basis of economics. The
main types and the dilemmas of this most influential of all Western moral
theories are described, e.g., act utilitarianism and rule utilitarianism; the
question of whether an increase in happiness is equally important as a
reduction in suffering. For the first time, the most important critical
arguments against utilitarianism are formulated.
In Chapter 8 entitled Some Major
Criticism of Utilitarianism, the main criticisms are discussed in detail in
the context of economics. The subjects of analysis are:
1) Utilitarianists’
interest in the consequences of the existence of rules and institutions, not in
these rules and institutions as such; this “consequentialism” ignores the fact
that people value not only the results of their own actions but also the way
these results are achieved.
2) The focus of
utilitarianists on the maximization of the utility of the whole society and
their neglect of responsibilities of individuals towards particular groups of
people.
3) Ignoring by
utilitarianists of basic values other than happiness (e.g. equality).
4) Utilitarianists’
assumption about the commensurability of all possible values, which allegedly
can be reduced to only one value: utility.
Chapter 9, GDP and Friends,
presents a short but detailed critique of the GDP. As an alternative or
complement to GDP, two approaches are proposed: 1) objective indicators
of specific components of “welfare”, or so-called “social indicators” such as
longevity or education level; and 2) subjective indexes of self-rated
“happiness”. In this chapter, the first approach is presented, including
Amartya Sen’s views and his human development index.
In Chapter 10, Happiness, the
author elaborates on the discussion begun in the previous chapter by briefly
analysing the achievements of economists who develop the so--called economics
of happiness. He is particularly interested in the “Easterlin paradox” and its
possible justifications, and in recommendations that the economics of happiness
can offer politicians.
In Chapter 11, Why Equality?,
Beckerman describes a very old debate about distributive justice. His focus is
on the possibility of justification of egalitarianism and the question what
kinds of inequality are “just”. John Rawls’s “maximin” theory of justice and
critical arguments against it (e.g. Robert Nozick’s arguments) are presented in
detail.
In Chapter 12, What Equality?,
Beckerman deepens his analysis of the ideal of equality (justice). He asks the
question, what exactly should be equalised in accordance with this ideal
(income? welfare? opportunities? Amartya Sen’s capabilities?). The
author tries to assess these various concepts, taking into account not only
justice but also other ethical ideals, such as responsibility for one’s own
actions.
Chapters 13 and 14, entitled The
Boundary of Society: The Boundary in Space and The Boundary of Society: The Boundary in Time,
respectively, are about the question of proper geographical and temporal
“boundaries” of society whose welfare economists try to maximize. Beckerman
states: “Many of the most important applied economic policy problems today go
well beyond the boundaries of any individual country or any particular slice
of time. So we have to ask ourselves how far we should extend our
distributional concern across space and time.” (p. 154)3.
In Chapter 15, Discounting the
Future, Beckerman outlines the factors that influence the level of
discount rate used in cost-benefit analysis. He analyzes the benefits of public
investment projects. Their consequences often reach far into the future and are
important for future generations. Beckerman reveals the decisive role of value
judgements which determine the discount rate (e.g., their effect is an
arbitrary assessment of the utility of future generations as compared with the
utility of people who live today).
Chapter 16 of the book, Valuing
Life, considers assessment of the value of human life for cost-benefit
analysis. The net output method and revealed preference method (revealed on the
market or in various surveys) are presented. Beckerman extensively describes
the critical arguments against these methods, including the argument of John Broome
that public investment projects that change the risk of death cannot be
assessed on the basis of a compensation test. From the point of view of
politicians who represent the whole society, rather than the point of view of
an individual citizen, abandoning such a project equals the certainty of
someone’s death. It means that no compensation payment can be seen as high
enough to balance the losses incurred as a consequence of giving up this
project.
*
Beckerman has a very
rare gift for simple explanations of very complex and important issues. In
addition, the problems he describes are among the most surprising and exciting
in economics. His book is full of deep ideas, penetrating remarks, detailed
information and quotations from the latest publications. In effect, this
erudite and witty book extends the reader’s horizons and stimulates the
imagination.
However, in my opinion, the general
framework in which the author presents his detailed arguments has one important
shortcoming. Using many examples, Beckerman over and over again emphasizes the
alleged “value-loadedness” of welfare economics. The last chapter of the book
entitled Overview: Value Judgements in Welfare Economics is a
summary of all these approaches. Generalizing his arguments, the author points
out that the variant of the allocation of goods recommended by most economists
is not the best variant. The reason that welfare economics recommends an allocation
of goods which is not optimal, according to Beckerman, are “numerous value
judgements ... embedded, sometimes deeply, in the structure of welfare
economics.” (p. 226). Here are some examples of these “value judgements”:
1. Economists who
recommend a specific allocation of goods in an economy as a Pareto--optimal
allocation ignore the fact that prices in this economy depend, among others, on
distribution of income between members of society. Any change of this distribution
of income causes changes of these prices which, in turn, causes a new
allocation of goods that becomes the Pareto-optimal allocation. The result is
that economists who recommend an optimal allocation of goods in an economy as a
Pareto-optimal allocation implicitly accept the existing income distribution in
this economy.
2. Economists assume
that consumers’ decisions adequately represent their preferences and their
pursuit of “welfare”. Yet, many decisions of buyers are influenced by asymmetric
information. Such decisions often do not reflect real preferences of these consumers.
Additionally, sometimes fulfilling preferences cannot be seen as pursuit of
welfare, since certain kinds of preferences cannot be accepted but should be
censored (e.g., sadists’ preferences). Once again, economists who search for
the optimal allocation of goods in an economy ignore these generally known
problems.
3. Likewise,
economists ignore problems with constructing a rational connection between
individuals’ welfare and social welfare (an example of such problem is
described by Arrow’s impossibility theorem). In effect, methods of linking
social welfare with the welfare of individuals are unavoidably arbitrary. The
objection to arbitrariness also affects the ideal of justice and the
concretization of this ideal. For example, should politicians who take
collective decisions equalize income or perhaps should they equalize Amartya
Sen’s capabilities? And if they should equalize income, should it be, e. g., income
per capita or household income?
4. Traditionally, as
the best variant of the allocation of goods, economists prefer the variant
which maximizes the utility of consumers. Yet Beckerman points out that such an
economic goal is not obvious at all. As Robert Nozick and Amartya Sen state,
utilitarianists ignore basic values other than happiness (e.g., the integrity
of certain laws, such as property rights).
5. Furthermore, when
recommending the optimal variant of allocation of goods in an economy,
economists very often ignore interests of inhabitants of other countries and
interests of future generations.
6. Economists’
decisions can be equally arbitrary about the level of the discount rate which
is used in the analysis and about the method of assessment of the value of human
life.
In my view, arguing this way,
Beckerman mostly describes not “impregnation” of welfare economics with ethical
value judgements, but numerous simplifying assumptions arbitrarily accepted by
welfare economists. Accepting these assumptions often results in detachment
from reality and reduces the practical importance of economic analysis. When
Beckerman states that welfare economics is not value-free objective science
(p. 3), one gets the impression that he sees welfare economics as a science
which is inherently different (“normative” and not “positive”) from physics,
biology and other empirical sciences. However, physicists and chemists also use
numerous simplifying assumptions which are similar to assumptions 1–6
enumerated above. For instance, it happens that physicists ignore the impact
of air resistance on the speed of objects which are falling in the
gravitational field, and chemists ignore the potential impact of contamination
of the investigated substance.
*
Sporadically,
Beckerman also uses other arguments for the thesis about value-loadedness of
welfare economics. Here are some examples:
1. Beckerman states that value judgements cannot be separated from
the rest of welfare economics so that it becomes “a pure value-free positive
economics”. In his view, the reason is that “economists’ personal value
judgements influence their choice of questions to study and their selection of
the relevant empirical information.” (p. 17).
Yet, the lengthy arguments regarding
the normative character of welfare economics do not concern value judgements,
which determine the choice of subject and the method of inquiry. Such methodological
value judgements (as Mark Blaug calls them) are accepted in all sciences
(Blaug 1992, chapter 5; Blaug 1998). They do not differentiate welfare economics
from – for instance - meteorology or geology, which are generally seen as
positive sciences building objective knowledge. Such value judgements that may
control the choice of simplifying assumptions used in analysis, as described
above, are in my opinion methodological value judgements in Blaug’s sense
(generally, they determine the method of investigation). Debates about the
normative character of welfare economics concern ethical, moral, aesthetic,
and ideological value judgements, and not methodological value judgements4.
2. Analyzing the example of the minimum wage, Beckerman argues that
when economists recommend certain economic policies, they always accept a
specific mix of statements of fact and value judgements. For instance, when
economists opt for minimum wage legislation, the choice is motivated first by
the fact that, in their opinion, the minimum wage will lead to an increase of
the lowest category of earnings; and second, their aim is to reduce differences
of income in society (pp. 27–30). Consequently, Beckerman concludes that
welfare economics is not a value-free objective science.
In my opinion, this conclusion is
wrong. Surprisingly, in Beckerman’s monograph I didn’t find the author’s answer
to Pieter Hennipman’s (and Yew-Kwang Ng’s, and George C. Archibald’s)
convincing arguments for the thesis that welfare economics is a positive
science, as value-free as, e.g., astronomy. The argument was repeated by Hennipman
many times during debates with Ezra J. Mishan and Mark Blaug (Hennipman 1976,
1982, 1984a, 1984b, 1992, 1993; cf. Archibald 1959, pp. 320–321, Ng 1992, p. 6)5. Hennipman holds that welfare
economics, like any other empirical science, may be seen as a set of positive
statements that can be classified as true or false. They are true or false
statements about the efficiency of different means of pursuing given ends. For
instance, in the case of chemistry, the end can be production of aspirin, and
in the case of welfare economics, the end can be maximization of total surplus.
Whether someone will use chemistry or welfare economics to reach the ends
depends on whether he or she values aspirin or total surplus. Such action, as every
conscious action, does require a certain value judgement. But that does not
mean that either chemistry or welfare economics is itself “value loaded”.
Notes
1 Wilfred Beckerman was born in 1925 and
is Emeritus Fellow of Balliol College in Oxford and Visiting Professor of
Economics at University College London. He has also worked as an adviser for
the World Bank, United Nations, OECD and ILO.
2 See Wilfred Beckerman, Economics as
Applied Ethics. Value Judgements in Welfare Economics, Palgrave MacMillan
2011, 274 pages.
3 In the Annex to Chapter 13, after
analyzing the crucial aspects of international distributive justice, Beckerman
proposes a specific solution for the problem of how to allocate costs of
preventing climate change among various countries. Further, in Chapter 14, he
analyses questions such as: “Do we have obligations to future generations?”;
“Do future generations have the right to inherit the same environment as exists
now?”, and “What is a just distribution of the Earth’s resources between us and
future generations?” (p. 178).
4 Likewise, in Beckerman’s view, choices
of definitions are value judgements as well. For instance, on pp. 150–153, the
author describes the choice of a specific definition of “income” used in comparisons
of various countries at various times as a value judgement (e.g., it can be an
annual income, a lifetime income, an individual’s income, a family’s income, or
a household’s income). The result is that in Beckerman’s sense every physical
science (e.g., physiology) is full of value judgements, since every physical
science is full of definitions.
5 As we know, the result of this
discussion was that Mishan stopped defending the concept of ”normative” welfare
economics and accepted Hennipman’s position (see Mishan 1984; cf. Czarny 2010
p. 165).
References:
Archibald, G.C.
(1959) Welfare Economics, Ethics, and Essentialism, Economica, Vol. 26,
No. 104.
Blaug, M. (1992) Methodology
of Economics. Or How Economists Explain, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Blaug, M. (1998) The
Positive-Normative Distinction, in: The Handbook of Economic Methodology,
ed. by J. B. Davis, D. W. Hands and U. Mäki, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham et al.
Czarny, B. (2010) Pozytywizm
a sądy wartościujące w ekonomii, Oficyna Wydawnicza SGH, Warszawa 2010.
Hennipman, P. (1976) Pareto
Optimality: Value Judgement or Analytical Tool, in: Relevance and
Precision. From Quantitative Analysis to Economy Policy, ed. by J. S.
Carmer, A. Heertje, A., P. Venekamp, North-Holland, Amsterdam.
Hennipman, P. (1982) Welfare
Economics is in Impasse: Some Observations on Mishan’s Vision, De
Economist, No. 4.
Hennipman, P. (1984a)
Normative or Positive: Mishan’s Half-Way House, De Economist, No. 1.
Hennipman, P. (1984b)
The Nature of Welfare Economics: A Final Note, De Economist, No. 2.
Hennipman, P. (1992) The
Reasoning of a Great Methodologist: Mark Blaug on the Nature of Paretian
Welfare Economics, De Economist, No. 4.
Hennipman, P. (1993) Moving
in Circles: Blaug Once Again on the Nature of Paretian Welfare Economics,
De Economist, No. 2.
Mishan, E. (1984) Welfare Criteria: Concluding Comments, De Economist, No. 2.
Ng, Y-K. (1992) Welfare Economics: Introduction and Development of Basic Concepts, Macmillan, London.
Mishan, E. (1984) Welfare Criteria: Concluding Comments, De Economist, No. 2.
Ng, Y-K. (1992) Welfare Economics: Introduction and Development of Basic Concepts, Macmillan, London.